For this lecture, read Nietzsche’s Beyond Good & Evil , Preface & Chapter 1, and his essay On Truth & Lies In A Non-Moral Sense.

Nietzsche Warhol

This week is the first without an ‘ism’ as a subject, though we could call this week “Nietzscheanism: Nietzsche and Bataille” if it didn’t sound redundant.  Nietzsche, while similar to Schopenhauer and Kierkegaard, was a very individualistic thinker, pushing beyond the subjectivism of Kierkegaard.  Like Kierkegaard, Nietzsche denounced the hypocrisy of everyone, but abandoned his religion, nation, and race.  He knew this about himself, and wrote that he feared acquiring followers, disciples who valued his ideas and individual thinking more than their own.  However, followers he did acquire, particularly among later French philosophers we will study such as Bataille, Sartre, Foucault, Deleuze, Derrida, and Baudrillard, all of whom were influenced by the German philosophers Hegel, Nietzsche and Heidegger.  These thinkers extended the ideas of Nietzsche and Heidegger in new directions.

Nietzsche 1882

Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche (1844 – 1900 CE), the great mustachioed one, came from a long line of protestant Lutheran preachers, five generations deep on his father’s side.  Unfortunately, Nietzsche’s father died when he was five years old, suffering both physically and mentally from debilitating insanity.   Nietzsche as a boy wondered why both his father, a passionate preacher loved by the community, and older brother suffered and died for no apparent reason in spite of being Christian.  Though his family sent the boy to school to become a preacher and theologian, like Hegel, Heidegger and many other German thinkers Nietzsche rebelled and turned to philosophy after a brief period of turning to mathematics.  Nietzsche also studied philology, a now forgotten subject similar to social and anthropological linguistics.

Napoleon on Horseback at the St Bernard Pass by Jacques-Louis David

As a youth, Nietzsche held many French authors in high esteem, such as the French aphorists La Rochefoucauld and Chamfort, and in Nietzsche’s writings he frequently praised French culture and derided German culture as base.  In one passage, he lamented that Germans, fond of cheese and beer, clearly do not know what a healthy constitution consists in.  This may have helped him get a following amongst later French Nietzscheans.  Like Hegel, Nietzsche revered Napoleon, seeing him as a great leader of the new European age.  As a youth, Nietzsche admired the leaders of the world’s religions such as Zarathustra, Jesus, Confucius, and Mohammed, as well as the philosopher Spinoza, who also had a larger unitive vision of reality.

Lucerne switzerland
Richard Wagner

From 1869 Nietzsche was a professor of philology at the University of Basel, Switzerland’s third largest city bordering both France and Germany.  He was close with many of his colleagues, and frequently visited the composer Wagner and his wife Cosima in nearby Lucerne.  At first Nietzsche revered Wagner, writing that he was one of the great geniuses of the age, and the two bonded over a love of Schopenhauer.  Wagner read Nietzsche’s Birth of Tragedy, and wrote to Nietzsche that he was, along with his wife, the closest person by far to Wagner himself.  Then Wagner became increasingly Christian, German-nationalist, and antisemitic, and his music became full of flash and pomp.  Nietzsche, quite opposed to traditional religion, nationalism, and antisemitism, wrote to Wagner imploring him to see the light.  Wagner replied with silence, and the friendship ended, to Nietzsche’s great sorrow.

Apollo Statue

While Wagner adored Nietzsche’s first book, The Birth of Tragedy (1872), it was shunned by academics and ignored by the public.  Nietzsche argued that the ancient Greeks were not simply rationalists as was often said in Nietzsche’s time and still is today.  He argued that there were two opposite strains in Greek society, the Apollonian (order, reason and law) and the Dionysian (chaos, emotion and revolt).  Apollo was the ancient Greek god of knowledge, and Dionysus was the god of ecstasy, intoxication and transformation.  These opposite gods are similar to Kant and Hegel’s conception of understanding, which orders, and reason, which is free, however the freedom of Dionysus is less the use of logic and more the use of other things.

Michelangelo's Bacchus Dionysus

Nietzsche suggests that this is quite human, and societies that flourish do not simply become rational and reasonable but struggle to both restrain and escape restraint, to categorically understand and transcend categorical understanding, engaging in both science and art.  This is very similar to Hegel’s historical dialectic of dogmatism and skepticism we studied last time.  However, following Schopenhauer’s criticism of Hegel, Nietzsche identifies the opposite of understanding not as reason, confined by logic, but will, not as mathematical science but as creative expression.

heraclitus bust

Amongst the ancient Greek philosophers, Nietzsche particularly admired Heraclitus, who he said was closer to his own thought than any other thinker.  In Nietzsche’s philosophical autobiography, Ecce Homo (“Behold the Man” in Latin, the words of Pontius Pilate as he reveals Jesus to the crowd who condemns him), Nietzsche writes, “In (Heraclitus’) proximity I feel altogether warmer and better than anywhere else… The affirmation of passing away and destroying, which is the decisive feature of a Dionysian philosophy; saying Yes to opposition and war; becoming, along with a radical repudiation of the very concept of being – all this is clearly more closely related to me than anything else thought of date”.  Nietzsche also identified Heraclitus’ thought with that of Schopenhauer, and quoted Schopenhauer in explaining the philosophy of Heraclitus.

chimp thinking

Nietzsche, like Heraclitus, enjoyed comparing humans to apes, to humble us and encourage us to evolve beyond what we are, writing, “If God created the world, then He made man His ape, to provide constant amusement during His overlong eternities.”  Heraclitus wrote, a favorite quote of mine, “To a god the wisdom of the wisest man sounds apish.  Beauty in a human face looks apish too.  In everything we have attained the excellence of apes.”

Sextus Empiricus

While many have compared Nietzsche’s philosophy to Pyrrhonian skepticism, Nietzsche only rarely mentions ancient skeptics, by which he means Greek Pyrrhonians.  Like Nietzsche, the Pyrrhonians believed that truth is perspective and appearance, and that this view was not nihilistic but rather life affirming.  Nietzsche was likely acquainted with Pyrrhonism through secondary sources.  There is no evidence he had read the works of Sextus Empiricus, the major ancient textual source for Pyrrhonian skepticism.  He did purchase, read and praise a book on Pyrrhonism in 1888, but as this was at the very end of his writing career it could have had no effect on the majority of his own work.

Nietzsche Sick Seaside

Nietzsche became sick with stomach problems and other health matters, which would plague him for the rest of his life, and in 1879 he resigned his professorship.  Nietzsche wrote that sickness was “the teacher of great suspicion”, and was well aware that, as a philosopher who argued that all philosophy is personal interpretation, he wrote in praise of strength and independence as a sickly individual.  For the next ten years, until 1889, he traveled largely in France and Italy, seeking a warm climate in winters for his ailments, and wrote several books which are celebrated today but in their time almost entirely unnoticed.

thus spoke zarathustra

Nietzsche’s great works of this period include his Human All too HumanThe DawnThe Playful Science (often translated “The Gay Science”, but as the famed translator Kaufmann noted the word ‘gay’ has a different meaning since the sixties, and it should be understood as merry, irreverent, and joyful), Thus Spoke ZarathustraBeyond Good and EvilThe Genealogy of Morals, and The Twilight of the Idols (subtitled: How to Philosophize with a Hammer).  With Thus Spoke Zarathustra, he believed he had finally found his true voice and final philosophy, and the books that follow are considered his definitive work.

Nietzsche_paul-ree_lou-von-salome

It was also during this period that Nietzsche befriended Paul Ree, who introduced him to Lou Salome, and the three traveled together while Nietzsche shared and developed his ideas with them until their friendship broke apart in 1883, the year he finished Thus Spoke Zarathustra and entered his final definitive period.  There is a famous photo of the three friends with Nietzsche and Ree yoked to a cart, and Salome in the cart holding a whip, likely taken at a carnival.  Nietzsche had problems with women, confessing some of these problematic opinions in his early Untimely Meditations.  Just after warning against Kantian notions of objective truth, Nietzsche offers to share some of “my truths”, and suddenly begins a long rant about women.  Some, such as Derrida, consider Nietzsche’s display of his prejudice to be inspirational, as he seems to wear his problems on his sleeve rather than ignore them or declare them to be the objective truth.  Much as Judith Butler, who was influenced by both Nietzsche and Derrida, argues that gender is a performance, Derrida argued that Nietzsche shows us philosophy is a performance of subjective truth.

Lou Salome 1914

In his Untimely Meditations, Nietzsche wrote that when dealing with women, do not forget your whip, the most controversial statement he makes and certainly not a position Butler would endorse.  In the famous photograph taken years later, after Nietzsche had befriended Lou Salome, it is she who is holding the whip.  Nietzsche wrote later to Ree in 1882 that Salome was the most intelligent person he had ever met, just as he had admired the intelligence of Wagner’s wife Cosima years before.  After splitting with Ree and Salome, Nietzsche often complained that he could find no one who could understand his vision, and he longed to find people as or more intelligent and far seeing as himself.

Nietzsche sick

Tragically, in 1889 at the age of forty five, just as he was beginning to gain fame and popularity, his books being read and professors giving lectures about him, he had a period of great bliss and happiness, followed by a lapse into increasingly catatonic insanity.  According to the story, Nietzsche saw a fallen horse being beaten in the street, and he threw his arms around its neck, weeping uncontrollably.  After this, he said and wrote very little.  While some opposed to Nietzsche’s skeptical thinking have argued that insanity was the result of his philosophy, others who embrace Nietzsche’s thought, including Karl Jaspers, one of Nietzsche’s first major interpreters and also a psychiatrist, have argued that Nietzsche’s eventual insanity was the result of a genetic condition he inherited from his father.

Nietzsche painting munch

Nietzsche saw himself as a great awakening, as one who saw that truth is interpretation and perspective.  Hegel argued that reality is both objective and subjective, a social construct, but Hegel tried to systematize subjectivity to reveal the structure of objectivity.  Nietzsche saw himself as destroying the myth of the objective system, and much like Kierkegaard he hoped that those who understood him would transform reality and themselves as they saw fit, having the courage to make leaps of faith once they saw that it can be done.  An emotional and entertaining author, Nietzsche makes bold judgements, often involving great praise or condemnation, but he was not making pronouncements about final answers, but demonstrating the ability to continue to question.  This is why, as Nietzsche himself wrote, he had earned the right to be wrong as well as contradict himself in countless ways.  Rather than defend truth as a final form, he had hoped to inspire a great will to truth and the creation of meaning in others, a courage to plum the depths and kick the tires.

Karl Jaspers

Karl Jaspers argued that self-contradiction was the fundamental ingredient in Nietzsche’s thought, and that Nietzsche seems to have two opinions about everything, which is the reason that socialists and individualists, scientists and artists, theists and atheists, and all other varieties of opinionated people find passages of Nietzsche that they lovingly quote to support their own views or bitterly condemn as supporting the opposition.  Our capacity for understanding oversimplifies existence, and because noncontradictory understanding must remain on the surface great thinking often requires self-contradiction.  Nietzsche’s thought is not a system, but a passion, a journey to new truth unlike any before.  Jaspers said that to understand Nietzsche, you must also be in motion, must be passionate, and must be willing to discover new things about yourself.  Truth is something progressively revealed, but also fundamentally ambiguous, able to be interpreted and reinterpreted in countless ways.  These seem mutually exclusive, but only to that in us which demands final, closed answers.

nietzsche_thorak

Nietzsche did not want his texts to be read like newspapers, available to all regardless of ability.  There is no one way, so find your own way, Nietzsche implores the reader.  Nietzsche encouraged his readers to distrust him as he distrusts himself.  Truth, in the individual or society, should not need to be defended, but rather put into conflict, forcing it to rise to the occasion or perish.  Nietzsche wrote that if he was to pronounce a law that should not be broken, it would only be for the purposes of testing the individual who would be courageous enough to strengthen themselves by breaking it.  Suffering, error and contradiction are necessary in every great development, which Nietzsche argued the great must embrace and cherish.

Nietzsche Tightrope Diagram
Forain the tightrope walker

Nietzsche argued against the two extremes of morality and nihilism.  He saw Europe as entering a crisis after the Enlightenment, in which all objectivity, authority and morality were called into question.  Most would turn to morality and objectivity, giving their individuality to religion, science or politics without criticism in the hope of security.  Others would lose all faith and motivation, turning to nihilism and renouncing the ability to believe and create.  Between these two extremes, Nietzsche argues, is the tightrope walker, the one who faces the void, the absence of complete security and certainty, and decides to create meaning, to give their life some meaning needing no authority other than their own individuality.  Nietzsche distinguished himself from nihilists, saying he had never feared failing to find the way out of the hole of nothing and arrive at something.

Nietzsche humanity too mainstream meme

Nietzsche valued creativity (‘Schaffen’, in German), and praised the individual’s ability to out-think the herd.  Nietzsche at times said he was creating new values, new ideals, and at others that he was smashing all idols without replacing them with others.  Both these are true.  Nietzsche found values for himself, and for others who enjoyed them, but he wanted everyone to be free to find their own, and so permanent social idols were to be smashed and not replaced, but some ideal must be asserted by the individual to avoid the collapse into nihilism.  Like for Descartes, skeptical questioning leads to positive results, but unlike for Descartes, Leibniz, Kant and later positivists, Nietzsche’s positive result is individual and unavoidably involved contradictions.

confucius2

Nietzsche loved and hated humanity, celebrating human thought’s ability to rise above itself, to evolve unlike anything else in existence, while bitterly attacking it’s perpetual hypocrisy and cowardice.  This is similar to Confucius, with whom Nietzsche compared himself at a young age.  Like Confucius, Nietzsche said that he could not find a perfect man anywhere, but humanity, as it already was, was capable of endless possibility, of producing boundless truth, unbounded even by self-consistency or noncontradiction.  Human thought can overcome any obstacle it sets in its own path, and cannot grow without obstacles to conquer.  Human individuals, through thought, can observe themselves just as thought can observe itself, and through this gain freedom or impose limitations, as it fits in its time and place.

gorilla fight

Nietzsche often compared humanity to animals, as did Schopenhauer.  Nietzsche wrote that humanity is the most refined beast of prey, founding nations and making war, deceiving and trampling more effectively than any other beast, more courageous and cruel than any other animal.  When we cannot be beastial in act, we are beastial in thought.  However, unlike all other animals, humanity shows a far greater capacity for change and evolution, if not so much in physiology then in thought and technology.  Nietzsche viewed the human individual much as Schopenhauer viewed the world, as a will divided against itself, as an ecosystem of drives.  Our various drives, which resemble those of every other human individual but also vary between any two individuals, help each other, fight each other, conceal each other, redirect each other, and invoke each other.

Train wreck Montparnasse 1895

We advance by way of errors and illusions.  False beliefs evolved over long periods, committing countless mistakes, to arrive in modern times.  Humanity considers itself the center of creation, the meaning of the cosmos, the most free being in spite of imposing the most restriction, capable of working miracles in defiance of physics, and then convinced that it holds the key to physics itself.  The idea of complete understandings, what Nietzsche regarded as a fundamental error, still drives much of human thought today, as it has for thousands of years.  Nietzsche distrusted Locke’s primary objective qualities and Rousseau’s general will of the masses.  Nietzsche was worried that in modern times humanity would celebrate its rise while it was falling, praising security while losing ingenuity, gaining incredible knowledge while losing inspiration and meaning.

nietzsche-colour

In order to view ourselves, we must construct a concept.  Not only are systems of thought social constructs, as we learned with Hegel, but the self is a self-construct as well as a social construct.  We must interpret ourselves just as we must interpret the world.  We evaluate ourselves, and others in terms of ourselves, continuously, loving and hating ourselves, repeatedly confiding in ourselves and distrusting ourselves, embracing ourselves and rejecting ourselves.  Nietzsche wrote that any individual who hates themselves is ready and willing to take revenge on others, similar to Freud’s conception of projection.  Nietzsche also wrote, “He who despises himself still respects himself as a despiser”.

alice-through-the-looking-glass

We are constantly deceiving ourselves about ourselves, as we are about others and the world.  We must view everything, including the thing which most matters to us, our self, through “the fictions of language and logic”, as Nietzsche says.  We forget and conceal in creating meaning.  While there are no complete and exclusive distinctions between any two things in life, we inscribe things as self-identical and distinct from all things in order to make sense of our world.  Recall that Schopenhauer saw self-conception and individuation as a basic problem, the knot of existence, the thing that turns the primal will against itself.  We interpret ourselves in light of how others have interpreted us, which we must interpret for ourselves based on the incompleteness of what they say and what they do.  We can overcome others with our opinions, and they can overcome our innermost understandings of ourselves with theirs.  We are and are not ourselves, just as Heraclitus wrote.  The selves and truths that we construct are both fictions and fact, intertwined.

klan march washington dc

Suppressed drives find means of release.  Often they turn inwards, and can become poisonous, life-denying rather than life-affirming.  Unlike hunger, most drives can subsist and be satisfied, if temporarily, like hunger, through ideas, judgements, and dreams.  Nietzsche hated revenge, and pity, both terrible forms of repression.  Nietzsche loved and hated superiority.  Individuals can be superior, but when individuals seek superiority in groups, they can discourage individual creativity, thinking beyond the herd mentality.  Nietzsche feared the revenge of the herd, which he labeled with the French term, ‘resentiment’, resentment with an ‘i’ in the middle.  The herd fear the new, individual and nonconformist, as these call objectivity and authority into question.

nazis marching with banners

We can always blame others, rather than ourselves, for our situation, avoiding individual responsibility for making our lives meaningful.  Nietzsche saw German nationalism and antisemitism rising in his own day.  Great individuals do not need to join groups to gain strength, nor blame other groups for their faults.  Recall Spinoza said the same about the bully and the drunk, who fail to understand the causes of their actions and thus feel that they are free.  By examining ourselves, and communicating about ourselves to others, we come to greater appreciations of the complexities of ourselves and of humanity as a whole.  Nietzsche, compared to other philosophers, was very honest about his faults and limitations.

lacan glasses off

To do anything, thought must limit itself, both a deception and a triumph.  Forgetting is a necessity of life.  Without it, we would not survive.  We only remember what we are driven to do, as well as what opposes this drive, a very Fichtean account of memory.  Nietzsche does not develop his picture of the drives or how they combat each other methodically.  Some drives are employed occasionally, others continuously, some are driven by excess, and others by lack.  Lacan, who attended Kojeve’s lectures on Hegel with Bataille, tried to systematize Nietzsche through Freud, arguing that we form an image of ourselves to mask the contradictions, and then repress or redirect whatever does not conform to this image, forever fighting reality which defies simple noncontradictory understandings.

wittgenstein

Nietzsche, like Wittgenstein, was critical of anyone who boiled down a situation to a single factor or essence.  Nietzsche himself ultimately rejected Schopenhauer’s conception of the will as primary, accepting that cowardice, along with will, are basic to the human being, if not to the world.  Our freedom is our transformation, for which we are continuously responsible.  While Nietzsche admired science, he saw scientism, the positivistic worship of science as objectivity and rationality, as a hindrance to science’s own progress.  Like Hegel, Nietzsche thought that science without contradiction is dead, a graveyard of concepts.  While Nietzsche argued that it is good to be acquainted with the sciences, the study of science should pave the way towards renouncing objectivity, absolute knowledge and universal facts.  Nietzsche feared, in the late 1800s, that science and politics were replacing religion, becoming the new dominant dogmatism.  Nietzsche wrote, “He who is willing to dismiss God clings all the more firmly to the belief in morality”, in an objective view.

Burned_at_Stake

Nietzsche acknowledges the problematic ways that interpretations, moralities and understandings justify themselves as law and thus disguise the joy in causing pain, the celebration of truths that persist as lies, the vengeance of what is labeled impartial.  Nietzsche believes, justly, that this is what has been understood for all of history but is rarely challenged.  Cultures set themselves apart from others through ideology, including the internal divisions of class and ethnicity.  Claims of objectivity, authority and morality are always directed by one group of people against another.  Morality is a great cause of immorality, and thus must eventually turn on itself, and judge itself, as the heresies and revolutions within Christian history attest.

jesus-christ-love

Nietzsche wrote, “Basically, there was only one Christian, and he died on the cross”.  He considered it the “irony of world history” that Christianity abandons and inverts the example of Jesus.  Similar to but beyond Kierkegaard, Nietzsche condemned Christianity for preaching absolute values when individuals must come to understand morality authentically for themselves, not universally throughout the group as a whole.  Nietzsche holds the same contempt for claims to objectivity in politics and science.  Imposition of objectivity is destructive for the possibilities of life and thought, a “castration according to Nietzsche in a term that would appeal to Freud.

Constantine

Nietzsche argued that, like himself, Jesus was an immoralistteaching people to free themselves from judgement and authority, writing, “Jesus took sides against those who judge: he wished to be the destroyer of morality”.  If one thinks that ethics is nothing more than morality, universal rules, this is a very unethical position, but if one thinks that ethics extends beyond morality, requiring individual interpretation in each situation, it demands continuous, individual responsibility.  Nietzsche was well aware that when Jesus was asked which is the most important commandment, he said to love others, which is not one of the commandments.  Jesus also taught that enemies should be loved, and outcasts embraced, overturning social convention.  When Constantine, the Roman Emperor, called Christians together to figure out which books should be bound together as the Bible, some Christian groups argued that the Old Testament, the Jewish Torah, should not be included, as Jesus had overturned the old law and shown the god of the Old Testament to be false.  Constantine decided to keep the Old Testament, and persecute Christian sects that disagreed.

superman

\Nietzsche wrote that he wanted humanity to become less universalized and more specialized.  Rather than try to totalize the knowledge, as Hegel had attempted, Nietzsche wanted knowledge to wander, to spread out and conflict with itself.  Like Heraclitus, Nietzsche argued that some are superior, rising above others, but foolishly choose to believe that they know the truth for everyone including themselves.  Only the greater ‘superman (Ubermensch in German), comes to realize that they do not need to know the truth for everyone but only construct greater truth for themselves.

confucius right side

This elevates and enables humanity as a model to follow far more than the one who considers their superiority to be universal supremacy and objectivity.  The superior who pronounce themselves to be objective fear failure, as this would threaten to dethrone their supremacy, but the superman embraces failures and faults, and has earned the ability to learn from and own their imperfections.  Confucius spoke similarly about the noble person, who is tough on themselves but easy on others.

Zarathustra Zoroaster

Thus Spoke Zarathustra (1885), the book which brought Nietzsche to his final definitive philosophy, is often quoted regarding the superman.  Nietzsche believed that the Persian prophet Zarathustra, one of the first monotheists, was the first dualist to exclusively separate good from evil, so Nietzsche has Zarathustra become the first to see beyond exclusive and eternal distinctions of good and evil, to recognize the error of his dualism, and see the interdependence and totality of the whole.  Zarathustra starts in his cave, where he has been contemplating existence, and then ‘goes down’ to the people.  First he encounters a forest dweller (very Indian), who is avoiding people to better love God as people are imperfect.  Zarathustra leaves him, goes into town and addresses the people, who have gathered to watch a tightrope walker.  Zarathustra addresses the crowd:

chimp with fruit

I teach you the superman.  Man is something that is to be surpassed.  What have you done to surpass him?  All beings have so far created something beyond themselves, and you want to be the ebb of that great tide, and would rather go back to the beast than surpass man?  What is the ape to man?

Once you were apes, and even yet man is more of an ape that any of the apes.  Even the wisest among you is only a disharmony and hybrid of plant and phantom.

Turner Fishermen at Sea

Truly, man is a polluted stream.  One must be a sea, to receive a polluted stream without becoming impure.

Man is a rope stretched between the animal and the superman, a rope over an abyss, a dangerous crossing.

What is great in man is that he is a bridge and not a goal.

Beyond-Good-and-Evil-by-Friedrich-Nietzsche

Beyond Good and Evil (1886) is considered to be one of Nietzsche’s greatest books, one of the best expressions of his thought.  In this book, Nietzsche attempts to push thought beyond categorical understandings of good and evil and of true and false to show the complexity of human meaning and life.  He starts this work asking:  Why do we want simple truth or suppose we can simply get truth? Philosophy seems like it has barely started, but it has been assumed that something in us wants absolute truth and can acquire it.  Nietzsche says that asking this question is perhaps the greatest risk.  If we question our ability to gain truth, it becomes possible that we will lose all hope for truth and turn to nihilism, which Nietzsche argues is equally as dangerous to human creativity and the process of life as the belief in objectivity.  Typically, thinkers have assumed that there must be absolute pure truth apart from or hidden within the messy world and various human opinions.  He writes:

shades of grey duality

This way of judging constitutes the typical prejudgment and prejudice which gives away the metaphysicians of all ages; this kind of valuation looms in the background of all their logical procedures; it is on account of this ‘faith’ that they trouble themselves about ‘knowledge’, about something that is finally baptized solemnly as ‘the truth’.  The fundamental faith of the metaphysicians is the faith in opposite values.  It has not even occurred to the most cautious among them that one might have a doubt right here at the threshold where it was surely most necessary. (BGE 2)

Kant silhouette

The falseness of a judgment is for us not necessarily an objection to a judgment… The question is to what extent is it life-promoting, life-preserving, species-preserving, perhaps even species-cultivating, and we are fundamentally inclined to claim that the falsest judgments (which include the synthetic judgments a priori) are the most indispensable for us, that without accepting the fictions of logic, without measuring reality against the purely invented world of the unconditional and self-identical, without a constant falsification of the world by means of numbers, man could not live, that renouncing false judgments would mean renouncing life and a denial of life.  To recognize untruth as a condition of life, that certainly means resisting accustomed value feelings in a dangerous way, and a philosophy that risks this would by that token alone place itself beyond good and evil. (BGE 4)

Kant Hegel comic

What provokes one to look at all philosophers half suspiciously, half mockingly, is not that one discovers again and again how innocent they are, how often and how easily they make mistakes and go astray, in short, their childishness and childlikeness, but that they are not honest enough in their work, although they all make a lot of virtuous noise when the problem of truthfulness is touched even remotely.  They all pose as if they had discovered and reached their real opinions through the self-development of a cold, pure, divinely unconcerned dialectic (as opposed to the mystics of every rank, who are more honest and doltish, and talk of ‘inspiration’), while at bottom it is an assumption, a hunch, indeed a kind of ‘inspiration’, most often a desire of the heart that has been filtered and made abstract, that they defend with reasons they have sought after the fact.

Yes We Kant Meme

They are all advocates who resent that name, and for the most part even wily spokesmen for their prejudices which they baptize ‘truths’, and very far from having the courage of the conscience that admits this, precisely this, to itself, very far from having the good taste of the courage which also lets this be known, whether to warn an enemy or friend, or, from exuberance, to mock itself.  The equally stiff and decorous tartuffery of the old Kant as he lures us on the dialectical bypaths that lead to his ‘categorical imperative’ really lead astray and seduce, this spectacle makes us smile, as we are fastidious and finds it quite amusing to watch closely the subtle tricks of old moralists. (BGE 5)

confessional booth

Gradually it has become clear to me what every great philosophy so far has been: namely, the personal confession of its author and a kind of involuntary and unconscious memoir… Accordingly, I do not believe that a ‘drive to knowledge’ is the father of philosophy, but rather that another drive has, here as elsewhere, employed understanding (and misunderstanding) as a mere instrument.  But anyone who considers the basic drives of man…will find that all of them have done philosophy at some time, and that every single one of them would like only too well to represent just itself as the ultimate purpose of existence and the legitimate master of all the other drives. (BGE 6)

It is perhaps just dawning on five or six minds that physics, too, is only an interpretation of the world (to suit us, if I may say so!) and not a world-explanation. (BGE 14)

Schopenhauer photograph

There are still harmless self-observers who believe that there are ‘immediate certainties’, for example, ‘I think’, or as the superstition of Schopenhauer put it, ‘I will’, as though knowledge here got hold of its object purely and nakedly as ‘the thing in itself’, without falsification on the part of either the subject or the object…I shall repeat a hundred times, we really ought to free ourselves from the seduction of words!  (BGE 16)

With regard to the superstitions of logicians, I shall never tire of emphasizing a small terse fact, which these superstitious minds hate to concede: namely, that a thought comes when ‘it’ wishes, and not when ‘I’ wish, so that it is a falsification of the facts of the case to say that the subject ‘I’ is the condition of the predicate ‘think’.  IT thinks. (BGE 17)

super market

In what strange simplification and falsification man lives!  One can never cease wondering once one has acquired eyes for this marvel!  How we have made everything around us clear and free and easy and simple!  How we have been able to give our senses a passport to everything superficial, our thoughts a divine desire for wanton leaps and wrong inferences!  How from the beginning we have contrived to retain our ignorance…and only on this now solid, granite foundation of ignorance could knowledge rise so far, the will to knowledge on the foundation of a far more powerful will: the will to ignorance, to the uncertain, to the untrue, not as its opposite, but as its refinement!  Even if language, here as elsewhere, will not get over its awkwardness, and will continue to talk of opposites where there are only degrees and many subtleties of gradation…here and there we understand it and laugh at the way in which precisely science at its best seeks most to keep us in this simplified, thoroughly artificial, suitable constructed and suitable falsified world, at the way in which, willy-nilly, it loves error, because, being alive, it loves life. (BGE 24)

Descartes and Queen Christina

Take care, philosophers and friends, of knowledge, and beware of martyrdom, of suffering ‘for truth’s sake’, even of defending yourselves…as though ‘the truth’ were such an innocuous and incompetent creature as to require protectors! (BGE 25)

In all seriousness, the innocence of our thinkers is somehow touching and evokes reverence, when today they still step before consciousness with the request that it should please give them honest answers… A philosopher has nothing less than a right to ‘bad character’, as the being who has so far always been fooled best on earth.  He has a duty to suspicion today, to squint maliciously out of every abyss of suspicion… Why couldn’t the world that concerns us, be a fiction?… Shouldn’t philosophers be permitted to rise above faith in grammar? (BGE 34)

child playing with blocks

One should not dodge one’s tests, though they may be the most dangerous. (BGE 41)

A man’s maturity consists in having found again the seriousness one had as a child at play. (BGE 94)

A people is a detour of nature to get to six or seven great men.  Yes, and then to get around them. (BGE 126)

Nietzsche's sister greets Hitler

It was a shame, especially given this last line, that Nietzsche was used by some Nazis, thanks to the efforts of Nietzsche’s sister, to support their ideas of the rising German will of the master race, taking Nietzsche’s individualism and twisting it into a racial and social doctrine.  Nietzsche intended his words for individualists, as he says over and over again, and he attacked both nationalism and racism as poisons that intoxicate the weak-minded.  The Nazis called the aryan race ‘supermen’ and other races the inferior sub-human ‘untermensch’.  Just as Nietzsche said that only an ocean could incorporate a poisoned stream into itself without becoming impure, Nietzsche said that the human race should be mixed together, including Jews, to create the greatest range of individuals and ethnicities possible.  He knew very well that this completely contradicted the proto-Nazis of his own time.

Caspar Wanderer above the sea of fog (mountains hiker)

When Nietzsche uses the term ‘Ubermensch’, he means the one who overcomes both themselves and their own culture, not those who embrace group identity to give meaning to their lives.  Nietzsche’s superior person is the visionary thinker or artist, not a nation or race.  Nietzsche called himself an ‘anti-anti-Semite’, moved to Switzerland and renounced his German citizenship to walk alone high in the mountains.  Surely this is how he would rather have been remembered.  As Nietzsche went catatonic, one of the last things he wrote in a letter to a friend was that, as Emperor, he was having all the anti-Semites shot.

Jaspers Nietzsche

In 1935, just after the Nazis had seized Germany and as some Nazis were using interpretations of Nietzsche to support their political movement, Karl Jaspers published his exhaustive book on Nietzsche’s philosophy to argue that Nietzsche was neither a nationalist nor a racist.  That year he was dismissed from his professorship by the Nazi government.  Jaspers wrote that Nietzsche was easy to read and intoxicating, but extensive reading can be frustrating as Nietzsche was not tied down to any judgement or system and contradicted himself almost completely.  In this, Jaspers says that Nietzsche is like humanity itself, and that anyone who wants to learn to think with the freedom of Nietzsche must suffer through the contradictions and lack of system to earn this for themselves.